International Borders: Yours, Mine, and Ours
International borders have become divisive issues in international and domestic politics. They have also become sites where the human rights of vulnerable persons have increasingly been documented as at risk. Policies of border harden- ing in the face of growing human mobility and other external threats—real and imagined—have made international borders focal sites of conflict at many levels. This Article argues that international law can reframe our understanding of bordering, leading to a more constructive approach to border management and greater respect for human rights. Borders are essentially institutions with the po- tential to settle coordination problems over territory. But of growing importance, they are also relational institutions that often have drastic effects on social and economic interactions. Their relational aspects require governance, for which international law has developed the law of neighborliness. In turn, the law of neighborliness requires, among other things, respect for mutually agreed covenants between sovereign states. Borders should not be presumed to pose inherent national security risks. Indeed, the presumption should be reversed: borders create zones where the need and obligation for friendly cooperation, including policies aimed at human rights protections, is at its highest.
I. Introduction
TOPOn June 7, 2010, an unarmed 15-year-old boy, Sergio Adrián Hernández Güereca, was playing with friends near the international border between El Paso and Ciudad Juárez. They were playing a game that involved running back and forth across a culvert, through which ran the international border between the United States and Mexico, touching a barbed wire fence on the American side, and running back. The boys attracted the attention of a Customs and Border Protection (CBP) agent, who rode up on his bicycle and detained one of them, while the other retreated back to the Mexican side of the border. Within just a few minutes, Agent Jesus Mesa Jr., standing on American soil, pointed his gun and took aim at the retreating teenager, who by now had reentered Mexico. He fired at least two shots, one of which struck the child in the face and killed him.1
SeeHernandez v. Mesa, 140 S. Ct. 735, 740–41 (2020).
The death of an unarmed boy at the hands of an agent of a neighboring state should raise serious questions not only about how states recruit and train border agents, but also about habits of thought regarding international borders. According to the United States Supreme Court, in response to a lawsuit filed by the Hernández family, CBP has “the responsibility for attempting to prevent the illegal entry of dangerous persons and goods” into the United States, and “the conduct of [their] agents positioned at the border has a clear and strong connection to national security.”2
Id. at 746.
Id. at 739.
This Article offers another view of international borders from the perspective of international law. It is motivated by the unquestioned association of international borders with crucial national security issues, not just in the courts of the United States, but also in a growing number of countries around the world. The national security assumption hides another assumption: that borders are constitutive of a state’s territorial sovereignty. Instead, this Article argues that borders are cooperative international institutions that provide collective international goods of stability. It reclaims the cooperative purpose of international borders, reflected in traditional sources of international law, as a basis for recalibrating the weight given to national security in discussions of how to manage and control borders. This part of the project is conservative, in that it restores an aspect of international borders that has been left behind in the politics of our times.
In this Article, I argue that international borders are not unilateral assertions of state sovereignty, and should not be governed as such. Instead, they are cooperative institutions to which states have consented to avoid international conflict. Bordering in international law originates as a collaborative project, with meaning (and obligations) for cross-border relationships and the international community as a whole. Borders should not be misconstrued as “sovereign,” and because of the relationships they govern, they should not be managed unilaterally. I advance an understanding of bordering that recognizes sovereign territoriality, but which views borders as not just territorial but as also relational. Bordering does not simply draw a dividing line; it also profoundly changes relationships between the divided polities. Border treaties formally create the category of neighbors, underscoring obligations of neighborliness. When sovereign states create borders, they also create border regions—special areas that require cooperative management. Bordering also creates discontinuous regulatory space, with relational consequences, potentially including smuggling, trafficking, and (now) unauthorized migration. The management problems in such space can become more acute the harder international borders become. A vicious cycle ensues when states double down on securitizing their borders.
As a relational institution, borders create the category of neighbor and obligations of good neighborliness. Good neighborliness has its roots in negative obligations—do not attack your neighbor, for instance. These are the core norms of the international legal system. But good neighborliness also requires states to live up to all aspects of their international obligations. Universal human rights overlay these discontinuities. While this obligation knows no territorial limits, border regions and policies to securitize them raise the risks of rights violations. I argue that as an institutional resource for managing collective international goods—order, stability, and the collective project of universal human rights globally—borders define neighbors that are governed by the international law of neighborliness. In turn, the law of neighborliness forbids states from using sovereignty and security justifications to exempt border regions from obligations under international human rights law.
The Article begins by describing the increasingly securitized border landscape of much of the world. Border zones are places of growing interdependence, but also of increasing securitization. The combination has some predictable consequences, namely, harsh enforcement measures that have increasingly violated the rights of border dwellers, crossers, and migrants. National security themes dominate the official response. Specious themes of “sovereign borders” misleadingly characterize international borders. Accountability for human rights violations tends to lag as a result.
The second Part explores the basis in international law for a more balanced view. I suggest a conception of bordering that acknowledges a relationship between sovereign neighbors who usually have functionally interdependent territorial zones. Bordering is valued not only by the neighbors that consent to them to divide territory, but to the international community as a whole, which values their stabilizing function. International treaty law reflects the collective value of border and boundary treaties.
The third Part draws through the theme of borders as relationships for understanding the international law of neighborliness. This body of law is a resource for interpreting rights and responsibilities between states in neighboring zones in which both have interests and obligations. Neighborliness embraces not only negative duties, but some positive duties as well. Most importantly, it requires states to live up to their international legal obligations. Aside from our humanity, aside from cosmopolitan obligations, and aside from the claims individuals and groups have a right to assert vis-à-vis their own state agents—and these, I will grant are primary—there is a state-centric reason for the cooperative, coordinated approach to human rights in border regions. Rights are universal, to be sure. But this understanding of borders replaces a “stand your ground” approach to border security with a more collaborative posture toward border management. The message is in the end very modest: minimally, border zones should not be exempt, in the name of sovereignty and security, from close human rights scrutiny. That’s the very least that should be expected from a good neighbor under such obligations by law. More ambitiously, my analysis calls in the longer term for cooperative border policies in a broad range of common endeavors, from environmental management to development to migration management.
The final Part provides some thoughts on ways forward to reach an appropriate balance between states’ legitimate interests in security and international human rights, none of which are especially radical. Conceptually, I hope to reconstitute an image of borders as shared institutional resources for managing a broader range of human values than recent trends have allowed. They define legally the physical contours of the sovereign state, but even more importantly, they are institutions for the cooperative management of interstate relations. States should not try to exempt themselves from human rights scrutiny in these spaces under the mantle of national security. On the contrary, they are obligated to maintain their international commitments in border spaces and to work cooperatively to solve border problems with neighboring states where necessary to do so.
II. Modern International Border Zones
TOPInternational borders mark jurisdictional divisions in what was once relatively continuous social, economic, and environmental space. As such, they create jurisdictional disjunctures that not only define the territory under states’ sovereign jurisdiction; they also affect the way billions of people live. Some simple statistical descriptions help to make this point. In 2016, almost 25 percent of the world’s population—some 1.87 billion human beings—lived within 100 kilometers of an international land border.4
Calculated using the LandScan database. See LandScan, Oak Ridge Nat’l Laboratory (2022), https://www.ornl.gov/project/landscan[https://perma.cc/53ZH-KWTF](last visited August 31, 2023). Approximately ninety-nine million people (1.32%) live within 5 kilometers, 200 million people (2.7%) within 10 kilometers, and more than 600 million people (8.05%) live within 30 kilometers of an international land border. These figures exclude coastlines.
Calculations based on data from author’s database of border crossings and population from LandScan. See LandScan, Oak Ridge Nat’l Laboratory (2022), https://landscan.ornl.gov/[https://perma.cc/5KBS-TXPP](last visited Aug. 31, 2023).
Tanvi Misra, CityLab/MapLab: Inside the Massive U.S. ‘Borderzone’, Bloomberg (May 14, 2018), https://www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2018-05-14/mapping-who-lives-in-border-patrol-s-100-mile-zone[https://perma.cc/RX9Y-YM4L].
UNWTO World Tourism Barometer and Statistical Annex, UNWTO eLibrary(Jan. 2020), https://www.e-unwto.org/doi/abs/10.18111/wtobarometereng.2020.18.1.1[https://perma.cc/7CTN-25LT].
The broad, variegated, and intense nature of near-border and transborder phenomena reflects the fact that border regions are dynamic and highly interdependent. Policies taken in one state can have effects across a border that are not considered when implementing the policy. Cross-border pollution is a classic example of a negative externality governed by a suite of international treaties.8
See, e.g., Convention on Long-range Transboundary Air Pollution, Nov. 13, 1979, 1302 U.N.T.S. 217, https://treaties.un.org/doc/Treaties/1979/11/19791113%2004-16%20PM/Ch_XXVII_01p.pdf[https://perma.cc/43M9-HFR4].
OECD, Illicit Trade: Converging Criminal Networks 5 (2016), https://read.oecd-ilibrary.org/governance/charting-illicit-trade_9789264251847-en#page1[https://perma.cc/3ZXA-N2BG].
Michael Kenwick & Beth A. Simmons, Pandemic Response as Border Politics, 74 Int’l Org. E36, E52 (2020). Positive externalities are possible as well. For example, if one country has an effective vaccine campaign it can potentially reduce infection rates in a neighboring state.
Eyal Benvenisti, Sovereigns as Trustees of Humanity: On the Accountability of States to Foreign Stakeholders, 107 Am. J. Int’l L. 295, 328 (2013).
The most obvious case is that of the European Union, and Frontex is an example. Note, however, that cooperation between states can be normatively problematic. For the critique of the legitimacy of European cooperation, see Hallvard Sandven, The Practice and Legitimacy of Border Control, Am. J. Pol. Sci. 1, 4 (2022). With respect to North America, see Matthew Longo, From Sovereignty to Imperium: Borders, Frontiers and the Specter of Neo-Imperialism, 22 Geopolitics 758, 768 (2017).
A. A Global Trend of Border Hardening
TOPDespite growing interdependence, there are gathering signs of border unilateralism. Evidence can be found in physical border security investments as well as in popular border discourse. Evidence of the first can be found, quite literally, on the ground. Satellite images show that the border crossings of the world—places where highways transect interstate borders—have far more elaborate inspection stations, official buildings, and gates than they have had at any point in the past twenty years.13
See Michael Kenwick et al., Infrastructure and Authority at the State’s Edge: The Border Crossings of the World Dataset, J. Peace Rsch. (forthcoming) (on file with author).
This point is developed and supported with examples in Michael R Kenwick et al., Border Walls as Cooperation Failures, (U. Pa. L. Sch., Pub. L. Rsch. Paper No. 23-13, 2023), https://ssrn.com/abstract=4343982[https://perma.cc/CHN9-HE6N].It is important to acknowledge that States may decide to govern some aspects of their shared border cooperatively, as the United States and Mexico have done in the past, then suddenly shift to a more unilateral stance. Matthew Longo identifies “co-bordering” as a global trend. Matthew Longo, The Politics of Borders: Sovereignty, Security, and the Citizen After 9/11, at 121 (2017).
For descriptive statistics, see Kenwick et al., supra note 14. See also Beth A. Simmons & Michael Kenwick, Border Orientation in a Globalizing World: Concept and Measurement, 66 Am. J. Pol. Sci. 853, 861 (2022); Ron E. Hassner & Jason Wittenberg, Barriers to Entry: Who Builds Fortified Boundaries and Why?, 40 Int’l Sec. 157, 166 (2015); Élisabeth Vallet & Charles-Philippe David, Introduction: The (Re)Building of the Wall in International Relations, 27 J. Borderlands Stud. 111, 113 (2012); David B Carter & Paul Poast, Why Do States Build Walls? Political Economy, Security, and Border Stability, 61 J. Conflict Resol. 239, 249 (2017).
Sean M. Topping, Defying Schengen through Internal Border Controls: Acts of National Risk-Taking or Violations of International Law at the Heart of Europe, 48 Geo. J. Int’l L. 331, 333 (2016).
For a 28-page list of all border controls implemented by members pursuant to Article 25 and 28 et seq. of the Schengen Borders Code, see Temporary Reintroduction of Border Control, European Comm’n Migration & Home Affairs, https://home-affairs.ec.europa.eu/policies/schengen-borders-and-visa/schengen-area/temporary-reintroduction-border-control_en[https://perma.cc/W5ZH-3AAV](last visited Sept. 18, 2023).
On U.S. policy in the Americas, see Nancy Hiemstra, Pushing the US-Mexico Border South: United States’ Immigration Policing Throughout the Americas, 5 Int’l J. Migration & Border Stud. 44 (2019). On Australia, see Amy Nethery et al., Exporting Detention: Australia-Funded Immigration Detention in Indonesia, 26 J. Refugee Stud. 88 (2013). On Europe, see Anneliese Baldaccini, Extraterritorial Border Controls in the EU: The Role of Frontex in Operations at Sea, in Extraterritorial immigration control 229 (2010); Maribel Casas-Cortes et al., ‘Good Neighbours Make Good Fences’: Seahorse Operations, Border Externalization and Extra-Territoriality, 23 Eur. Urb. & Reg’l Stud. 1 (2016).
Jaya Ramji-Nogales & Iris Goldner Lang, Freedom of Movement, Migration, and Borders, 19 J. Hum. Rts. 593, 593 (2020).
Exactly what animates the past two decades’ worth of border hardening is an active area of research. Certainly, there are some real threats, including transnational crime,20
A prominent U.S. example includes The White House, National Security Presidential Directive (NSPD-22) Combating Trafficking in Persons (2002), https://ctip.defense.gov/Portals/12/Documents/NSPD-22.pdf [https://perma.cc/9H5T-L89E].
An example at the international level is the establishment of the United Nations Office of Counter-Terrorism, through the adoption of G.A. Res. 71/291 (June 15, 2017). Border security is one of the organization’s key capacity-building emphases. SeeWhat We Do, U.N. Off. of Counter-Terrorism, https://www.un.org/counterterrorism/what-we-do[https://perma.cc/S5BU-B8UT](last visited Sept. 11, 2023).
Figures at a Glance,UNCHR, The UN Refugee Agency (June 14, 2023), https://www.unhcr.org/about-unhcr/who-we-are/figures-glance[https://perma.cc/5N76-RDKY].
Céline Cantat et al., Migration as Crisis, 67 Am. Behav. Scientist (forthcoming 2023) (manuscript at 1) (finding that “migration has become inseparable from a narrative of crisis.”).
Beth A. Simmons & Robert Shaffer, Border Anxiety in International Discourse, Am. J. Pol. Sci. (forthcoming) (on file with author) (defining border anxiety as “a heightened sense of instability or vulnerability perceived to be linked with a broad range of cross-border phenomena,” and emphasizing that it can often be exaggerated).
See generally David A. Shirk, The Escalation of US–Mexico Border Enforcement, in Borders & Border Walls: In-Security, Symbolism, Vulnerabilities (Andréanne Bissonnette & Élisabeth Vallet eds., 2020).
For the Office of Home Affairs’ campaign page, see Operation Sovereign Borders, Australian Gov’t, https://osb.homeaffairs.gov.au/[https://perma.cc/YCW8-95P7](last visited Sept. 11, 2023).
Introduced as the “Sovereign Borders Bill” in 2020. Sovereign Borders: International Asylum Comparisons Report, Home Office (Sept. 2020), https://freemovement.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/2022/11/Annex-A-Sovereign-Borders-International-Asylum-Comparisons-Report-Section-1-Drivers-and-impact-on-asylum-migration-journeys.pdf[https://perma.cc/4P9R-UKQF].
Matina Stevis-Gridneff, E.U. Border Agency Accused of Covering Up Migrant Pushback in Greece, N.Y. Times (July 18, 2021), https://www.nytimes.com/2020/11/26/world/europe/frontex-migrants-pushback-greece.html[https://perma.cc/2QHE-2VC5](referring to “a conundrum at the core of E.U. ambitions to tighten external borders by pooling resources and involving the bloc in the sensitive, zealously shielded work of sovereign border guards”).
Google Ngrams, https://books.google.com/ngrams/[https://perma.cc/ZCW9-L3V9](last visited Sept. 11, 2023).
Figure 1: Google Ngrams

Unfortunately, the risk is that such phrases may be used to justify policies. After all, every state has the right to defend its territorial sovereignty. This is the fundamental principle at the core of international law.30
For elaboration, see the discussion in Jack Goldsmith, Review: Sovereignty, International Relations Theory, and International Law, 52 Stan. L. Rev. 959 (2000).
B. The Incoherence of “Sovereign Borders”
TOPA central premise of this Article is that a phrase like “sovereign borders” is conceptually incoherent. As I will develop in the following Section, borders are cooperative institutions. They are not unilaterally determined, changed, or managed. They are certainly not sovereign entities. The fallacious rhetorical connection between “borders” and “sovereignty” is undoubtedly intentional. Hitching “open borders” to a loss of sovereignty and construction of a border wall with “reestablished American sovereignty” 31
See, e.g., Remarks by President Trump at the 45th Mile of New Border Wall, Reynosa-McAllen, TX, The White House (Jan. 12, 2021), https://trumpwhitehouse.archives.gov/briefings-statements/remarks-president-trump-45th-mile-new-border-wall-reynosa-mcallen-tx/) [https://perma.cc/B8ZJ-G3ED].
Commonly cited are the words of Max Huber, arbitrator in Island of Palmas (U.S. v. Neth.), 2 U.N. Rep. Intl. Arb. Awards 821, 838 (1928): “Sovereignty in the relations between states signifies independence. Independence in regard to a portion of the globe is the right to exercise there, to the exclusion of any other states, the function of a state.” See also Corfu Channel (U.K. v. Alb.), Judgment, 1949 I.C.J. 39, 43 (Apr. 9) (“By sovereignty, we understand the whole body of rights and attributes which a state possesses in its territory, to the exclusion of all other states, and also in its relations with other states.”).
Helmut Steinberger, Sovereignty, 10 Encyclopedia Disp. Installment 397, 408 (1987).
Clearly, then, borders do not “create” sovereign states. They are neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition for independent statehood. According to one authoritative formulation, “[n]one of the different sources of international law listed in Article 38(1) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice makes the existence of a state contingent upon the existence of a well-defined and undisputed territory.”34
North Sea Continental Shelf (Ger. v. Den./Ger. v. Neth.), Judgment, 1969 I.C.J. 3, ¶ 46 (Feb. 20). See also Giuseppe Nesi, Boundaries, in Research Handbook on Territorial Disputes in International Law 193, 195 (Marcelo Kohen & Mamadou Hébié eds., 2018) (arguing that “a boundary has no effect on the existence of a state”).
Montevideo Convention on Rights and Duties of States adopted by the Seventh International Conference of American States art. I, Dec. 26, 1933, 165 L.N.T.S. 19 (stating that a “defined territory” is one of the qualifications a “state as a person of international law should possess[]” according to the most widely accepted international convention on statehood).
For example, borders are not mentioned in the G.A. Res. 375 (IV), (Dec. 6, 1949).
U.N. Charter art. 2, ¶ 4.
III. Reframing Borders as Cooperative Institutions
TOPInternational borders and their fortification have been misleadingly, even dangerously, elided with the concept of sovereignty. I have argued this position is incoherent. International borders are properly understood as a central institution of modern international law and interstate relations. The transition from non-spatial rule to territorial rule forcibly disrupted dynasties, challenged spiritual authorities, and undermined political organization based on ethnic and kinship relations.38
SeeBeth A. Simmons & Hein E. Goemans, Built on Borders: Tensions with the Institution Liberalism (Thought It) Left Behind, 75 Int’l Org. 387, 389–91 (2021).
The principle of stability is traditionally deemed as the criterion for interpreting boundary treaties. See Charles de Visscher, Problèmes De Confins en Droit International Public 28 (1969).
International borders are essentially a public international good for consolidating states and coordinating their international relations. Under-provision of border stability risked “endanger[ing] the life of the State itself.”40
Dubai/SharjahBorder Arbitration, 91 Int’l L. Rep. 543, 578 (2009).
Malcolm N. Shaw, Boundary Treaties and Their Interpretation, 5 Queen Mary Stud. Int’l L. 239, 239 (2012) (claiming in his opening paragraph that “[b]oundary treaties are treaties, but are distinctive. They constitute a special category of treaties”).
There is vast empirical literature in international relations supporting this point. For an early statement and findings, see John Vasquez & Marie Henehan, Territorial Disputes and the Probability of War, 1816–1992, 38 J. Peace Rsch. 123 (2001).
These numbers reflect the total number of interstate land borders in “direct contiguity,” generated from the Correlates of War Dataset. Data Sets, Correlates of War, http://www.correlatesofwar.org/data-sets[https://perma.cc/YEZ4-JA86](last visited Sept. 11, 2023). See Beth A. Simmons, Border Rules, 21 Int’l Stud. Rev. 256, 260 fig.1 (2019).
Dan Altman, The Evolution of Territorial Conquest After 1945 and the Limits of the Territorial Integrity Norm, 74 Int’l Org. 490, 490 (2020).
Kenneth A. Schultz, What’s in a Claim? De Jure Versus De Facto Borders in Interstate Territorial Disputes, 58 J. Conflict Resol. 1059, 1059 (2014). (finding that “among states that have homeland territory disputes, the adoption of a legally binding border is associated with a significant reduction in the likelihood of future militarized conflict over the territory”). Seealso Nesi, supra note 34, at 150 (concluding that “[s]tates are more capable of peacefully carrying their relations and exercising sovereign rights when their territory is well defined—that is to say, when it can be easily identified”).
For these reasons, states have afforded special status to border agreements in international treaty law. First, states cannot unilaterally withdraw from or terminate border treaties. Long considered a part of customary international law,46
Shaw, supra note 41, at 242.
Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, May 23, 1969, 1155 U.N.T.S. 331.
Id.
Humphrey Waldock, Fifth Report on the Law of Treaties, 2 Y.B. Int’l L. Comm’n 1, 43 (1966).
Humphrey Waldock, Sixth Report on the Law of Treaties, 2 Y.B. Int’l L. Comm’n 51, 92–93 (1966).
Shaw, supra note 41, at 259 (in the context of the Eritrea-Ethiopia boundary commission).
Second, border agreements have special status in the law of state succession. Article 11 of The Vienna Convention on the Succession of States in Respect of Treaties provides that “[a] succession of States does not as such affect: (a) a boundary established by a treaty; or (b) obligations and rights established by a treaty and relating to the regime of a boundary.”52
Vienna Convention on Succession of States in respect of Treaties art. 11, Nov. 6, 1996, 1946 U.N.T.S. 3 [hereinafter Vienna Convention].
United States v. Texas, 143 U.S. 621 (1892) (holding that upon independence in 1840, Texas’s boundary with the United States was that established by treaty with Mexico in 1828).
Temple of Preah Vihear, (Cambodia v. Thai.), Judgment, 1962 I.C.J. 6 (June 15) (ruling that Cambodia succeeded to a 1904 boundary treaty concluded by France for Cambodia and Siam).
Vienna Convention, supranote 52, at art. 16 (“A newly independent State is not bound to maintain in force, or to become a party to, any treaty by reason only of the fact that at the date of the succession of States the treaty was in force in respect of the territory to which the succession of States relates.”).
Maurizio Ragazzi, Conference on Yugoslavia Arbitration Commission: Opinions on Questions Arising From the Dissolution of Yugoslavia, 31 Int’l Legal Materials 1488, 1499 (1992).
Third, and admittedly most controversially, international courts and jurists have held that boundary agreements can create obligations for third parties. For example, in the Eritrean/Yemen Arbitration case, the Tribunal found that boundary and territorial treaties can have legal effects on others. In deciding that Yemen could not claim the Hanish Islands in part because title to them had been established through the Treaty of Lausanne (to which Yemen was not a party), the Tribunal noted that “[b]oundary and territorial treaties made between two parties are res inter alios acta [a thing done between others] vis-à-vis third parties. But this special category of treaties also represents a legal reality which necessarily impinges upon third states, because they have effect erga omnes [for all].”57
Eritrea v. Yemen, 22 U.N. Rep. Intl. Arb. Awards 209, ¶ 153 (1998).
Shaw, supra note 41, at 239. There is growing consensus that boundary treaties indeed can bind third parties. See,e.g., Ulf Linderfalk, International Legal Hierarchy Revisited–The Status of Obligations Erga Omnes, 80 Nordic J. Int’l L. 1, 15 (2011).
Boundary regimes, such as those that regulate access to an international waterway,59
See Humphrey Waldock, Third Report on the Law of Treaties, 2 Y.B. Int’l L. Comm’n 5, 26–31 (1964).
Importantly, however, the International Court of Justice has held that joint territorial regimes between two states do not dispose of the rights of independent Third Parties. See Territorial and Maritime Dispute (Nicar. v. Colom.), Judgment, 2012 I.C.J. 624, ¶ 227 (Nov. 19).
a b 61">Waldock, supra note 59, at 31. See also Francesco Salerno, Treaties Establishing Objective Regimes, in The Law of Treaties Beyond the Vienna Convention 225, 226 (Enzo Cannizzaro ed., 2011) (referring to “existence of a prevailing general interest in the certainty of the law”).
Notably, resolving border and territorial disputes is considered an important factor for joining some international organizations such as NATO and the European Union. For NATO, settling such disputes “would be a factor in determining whether to invite a state to join the Alliance.” Study on NATO Enlargement, NATO (Nov. 5, 2008), https://www.nato.int/cps/en/natohq/official_texts_24733.htm[https://perma.cc/C8PQ-D4XK].
On “objective regimes” and their effect on third parties, see Reports of the International Law Commission on the Second Part of its Seven-Teenth Session and on its Eighteenth Session, 2 Y.B. Int’l L. Comm’n 169, 231 (1966); see also Arnold D. McNair, The Functions and Differing Legal Character of Treaties, 11 Brit. Y.B. Int’l L. 100, 102–03 (1930). Somewhat skeptically, see Carlos Fernández de Casadevante Romani, Objective Regime, in 7 Max Planck Encyclopedia Pub. Int’l L. 912 (2010).
Objective international boundary regimes are not limited to creating lines of division on the ground. In many historical cases, they have represented systems of governance in spaces of crucial shared interest. Some classic examples have established a regime of permanent neutralization, as did the agreements concluded by the Congress of Vienna on permanent Swiss neutrality,64
Swiss permanent armed neutrality was internationally recognized at the Congress of Vienna in 1815 by Russia, England, Prussia, Austria, and France. Thomas Curson Hansard, In Congress, At Vienna, June 8, 1815, 32 Parliamentary Debates from Year 1803 to Present Time 71, 182 (1816).
Convention Relating to the Non-Fortification and Neutralization of the Aaland Islands, Apr. 6, 1922, 9 L.N.T.S. 211.
Richard A. Barnes, Objective Regimes Revisited, 9 Asian Y.B. Int’l L. 97, 98 (2000).As examples, Barnes analyzes Antarctica, Outer Space, the Deep Seabed, the High Seas, and “Zones of Peace.” Id. at 106.
International border agreements that divide territory between sovereign states, then, are the fundamental cooperative international legal institution of the modern state system. Yes, they are lines of demarcation that confer rights, but the above discussion suggests that they are not legitimately created, changed unilaterally, or maintained as mere private deals between contracting parties. They are also institutions that constitute normative resources that govern interstate behavior. Stable borders can be reclaimed as a common resource for managing interstate conflict. The collective interest of the international community in international- borders-as-institutions is reflected in the territorial integrity norm of the U.N. Charter itself.67
U.N. Charter art. 2 ¶ 4.
IV. From Cooperative Bordering to Cooperative Border Management
TOPAt this point, readers may be wondering: what does all this state-centric talk of stability, cooperation, and international-borders-as-institutions have to do with human rights? How do borders as interstate institutions (focused on horizontalrelationships) address the universal rights of humans vis-à-vis states (vertical relationships)? How would it have made any difference to Sergio Adrián Hernández Güereca, or how might his family’s case look not-so-easy to dismiss under the mantle of national security if we viewed borders as cooperative institutions?
The dissenting justices in the Hernández decisions68
Hernandez v. Mesa, 582 U.S. 548, 557 (2017) (vacating and remanding the Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit’s decision affirming the District Court’s dismissal of the parents’ claims, and directing the Court of Appeals to address several questions); Hernandez v. Mesa, 130 S Ct. 735 (2020) (confirming the judgment of the Court of Appeals).
Hernandez, 582 U.S. 548, 557 (2017) (Breyer, J., dissenting).
Id. at 558.
Justice Breyer’s dissent then shifts to what international law has to say about such spaces. “[I]nternational law recognizes special duties and obligations that nations may have in respect to ‘limitrophe’ areas . . . . Those areas are subject to a special obligation of cooperation and good neighborliness . . . .”71
Id. at 559.
See generally Hernandez, 130 S Ct. at 756–57 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting).
A. From Division to Relations: Bordering as Neighboring
TOPTo return to our argument: There are two major consequences of bordering. International borders divide territory, and they define (and sometimes alter) legal and social relationships. Most analyses of international bordering concentrate on the former function. Territorial aspects of bordering emphasize the physically delimited jurisdictional exclusivity that borders imply, while downplaying how international bordering institutions and practices affect relationships between states and local communities. For example, Lord Curzon’s early-twentieth-century dictum that “[t]o claim territory is to deny it to others”73
Daniel-Erasmus Khan, Territory and Boundaries, in The Oxford Handbook of the History of International Law 225, 234 (Bardo Fassbender & Anne Peters eds., 2012).
Emer de Vattel, The Law of Nations 308 (Béla Kapossy & Richard Whatmore eds., 2008).
Alternatively, borders can be seen as essentially relational in nature. The world itself is a constellation of social relationships in space. What all borders do, by definition, is introduce divisions into the world. They “place at least two spaces in specific relation to one another.”75
Martina Löw & Gunter Weidenhaus, Borders That Relate: Conceptualizing Boundaries in Relational Space, 65 Current Socio. 553, 555 (2017).
All borders have this in common: they profoundly affect social relationships. At the most abstract level, there is no other reason to border. Some theorists conclude that a thing does not even qualify as a border if it has no social impact."</a
Anssi Paasi, Border Studies Reanimated: Going Beyond the Territorial/Relational Divide, 44 Env’t & Plan. A 2303 (2012). Paasi usefully describes a boundary as a sociological institution with both territorial and relational aspects. He sees borders not as “static ‘things’” but rather as “dynamic, unfolding relations.” Id. at 2304.
See Andreas Müller, Territorial Borders as Institutions: Functional Change and the Spatial Division of Authority, 15 Eur. Soc’y 353, 365 (2013) (describing “borders as reciprocal restrictions of influence”).
Public international borders, this view implies, are not mainly about claiming territory. They are about relationships. International bordering coordinates state neighbors: entities that are proximate to one another and that are juridically separate, but that are also in many ways likely to be interdependent. Beyond dividing, bordering is the recognition of neighboring states that share a common interest in coordinating their jurisdictional differences. This entails legal acknowledgment that my state has territorial limits on its sovereignty, and to require this mutual acknowledgement of my neighbor.78
Delimitation is the process of negotiating the location of an international border, and demarcation is how it is made visible in the landscape, e.g., through the placement of markers, signs, monuments, etc.
Nail is explicit about these ongoing aspects of dynamic bordering: “[B]order technologies must be maintained, reproduced, refueled, defended, started up, paid for, repaired, and so on. . . . Management in some form or another has always been part of their existence.” Nail, supra note 76, at 7.
Understood as a social process, international borders do not only have to be drawn—they have to be maintained. If the purpose of bordering in the first place is to realize jurisdictional authority in space—if territorial sovereignty is to become meaningful—then rules have to be created and enforced, routines need to be developed to avoid costly clashes, official communications near the border need to be established, and infrastructure needs to be repaired and replaced.80
On the international (and E.U.) law of good neighborliness, see Elena Basheska & Dimitry Kochenov, The Meso Level: Means of Interaction between EU and International Law ‘Good Fences Make Good Neighbors’ and Beyond . . . Two Faces of the Good Neighbourliness Principle, 35 Y.B. Eur. L. 562, 564 (2016) (formulating the obligation of good neighborliness as a “general principle [to be] accepted by all UN members”).
International law anticipates all of these ongoing needs in principles of good neighborliness, which Justice Breyer alludes to in his dissent above. The law of good neighborliness81
U.N. Charter pmbl.
Id. at art. 74. (“Members of the United Nations also agree that their policy in respect of the territories to which this Chapter applies, no less than in respect of their metropolitan areas, must be based on the general principle of good-neighborliness, due account being taken of the interests and well-being of the rest of the world, in social, economic, and commercial matters.”).
Laurence Boisson de Chazournes & Danio Campanelli, Neighbour States, in 7 Max Planck Encyclopedia Pub. Int’l L. 600, ¶ 6. (2006). Likewise, Tadeusz Gadkowski stresses that “[t]he good-neighborliness principle is thus undoubtedly an expression of the interdependence of the rights and interests of States bordering on each other and the requirement ensuing from this, namely that each State limit the activities that may cause damage outside its territory.” Tadeusz Gadkowski, The Principle of Good-Neighbourliness in International Nuclear Law, 12 Przegląd Prawniczy Uniwersytetu im. Adama Mickiewicza 265, 267 (2021)(emphasis added).
Paraphrasing the Declaration on Principles of International Law Concerning Friendly Relations and Cooperation Among States in Accordance with the UN Charter. G.A. Res. 2625 (XXV) (Oct. 24, 1970) [hereinafter The Declaration on Friendly Relations]. The Declaration on Friendly Relations, like the U.N. Charter as a whole, is based on the assumption of the “inviolability of territorial integrity.”
The “ensemble of norms” comprising the international law of neighborliness originated in the familiar negative duties of states, such as a duty to respect the full sovereignty of the neighbor, the inviolability of territorial sovereignty, and a duty to comply fully and in good faith with international legal obligations.85
See Bandung Conference: Asia-Africa 1955, ENCYCLOPEDIA BRITANNICA, https://www.britannica.com/event/Bandung-Conference[https://perma.cc/2CYQ-M43Q](last visited Oct. 10, 2023) (adopting a declaration on the promotion of world peace and cooperation). In addition, at least nine United Nations General Assembly (UNGA) resolutions that have grappled with defining good neighborliness. See Basheska & Kochenov, supra note 81, at 574.
See Gadkowski,supra note 84.
Bruno Simma, The Charter of the United Nations 1097 (1995) (concluding that “[t]he principle of good neighborliness rather sets a general, though nonetheless legally binding aim for policy; it is thus more than just a political principle.”); Boisson de Chazournes & Campanelli, supra note 84, ¶ 28 (concluding that “the concept of good neighborliness possesses some legal contours, though imprecise.”).
In the Haya de la Torre case, the ICJ suggested that the parties should “find a practical and satisfactory solution by seeking guidance from those considerations of courtesy and good neighborliness which, in matters of asylum . . . ,” thus nudging states in Latin America to conclude the Caracas Convention on Diplomatic Asylum in 1954. Haya de la Torre (Colom. v. Peru), Judgment, 1951 I.C.J. 71, 83 (June 13).
Malgosia Fitzmaurice & Olufemi Elias, Watercourse Co-operation in Northern Europe: A Model for the Future (2004). For the development of community of interest with respect to international watercourses, for example, see id. at 13–15.
Good neighborliness is directly and urgently relevant to the governance of proximate human and natural environments, shared resources, and interdependence.90
Edgardo Sobenes et al. The Environment Through the Lens of International Courts and Tribunals 549–59 (2022);
Joanna Kulesza, Human Rights Due Diligence, 30 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 265 (2021) (discussing this in the context of due diligence and international liability concepts).
Corfu Channel (U.K. v. Alb.), Judgment, 1949 I.C.J. 4, 22 (Apr. 9).
Gabˇcíkovo-Nagymaros Project (Hung./Slovk.), Judgment, 1997 I.C.J. 7, ¶ 142 (Sept. 25).
MOX Plant (Ir. V. U.K.), Case no. 10, Order of Dec. 3, 2001, 2001 ITLOS Rep. 95. Especially see the Separate Opinion of Judge Rudiger Wolfrum. Id. at 135.
Sobenes, supra note 91, at 553. Due diligence requirements are still being formulated. See Draft Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts, 2 Y.B. Int’l L. Comm’n 26 (2001), discussed in Kulesza,supra note 92.
Sobenes, supra note 91, at 556.
Damiano Canale, Walled Borders, Territoriality and Sovereignty: A Typology, 1 Athena – Critical Inquiries L., Phil. & Globalization 37, 47 (2021).
Some of the same principles have a clear place in the management of rights-respecting border spaces; arguably, even more so. International borders are relationships between states; but border controls—how states make their territorial sovereignty meaningful—are a means to govern populations.98
Id. (quotations omitted).
Löw & Weidenhaus, supra note 75, at 557; Ran Hirschl & Ayelet Shachar, Spatial Statism, 17 Int’l J. Const. L. 387, 391 (2019) (emphasizing states’ use of law to restrict various forms of mobility by creating a “new configuration” of the Weberian state).
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, Dec. 16, 1966, 999 U.N.T.S. 171.
One more thing should be obvious: good neighborliness requires states to live up to their obligations in international law. This is only to reiterate a fundamental norm that international customary and treaty law is binding. The importance of stressing this as a basic requirement of international good neighborliness is to highlight how extraordinary it would be to suspend international law compliance in precisely the areas of adjacency that neighborliness norms were originally designed to govern. For this reason, the Hernández dissenters defended the obligation of the United States to compensate its neighbors for the death of their son—as required by the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, which explicitly requires a remedy for such a violation, and which both the United States and Mexico signed, ratified, and were bound to follow.101
See, e.g., Kenwick et al., supra note 14, (presenting evidence that many border hardening projects are taken without consultation with a neighboring state and sometimes explicitly against their preferences).
B. Ways Forward for Neighbors and Human Rights
TOPNeighboring states share physical proximity, some degree of social and economic connectedness, and common obligations under international law. The lens of borders as cooperative institutions connects these commonalities in profound ways. We face a choice: double down on the borders-as-sovereignty narrative, which I have argued is fallacious, or draw on a broader conception of international borders as a shared resource for managing common interests and collective goods cooperatively.
What does this mean in practical terms? First, reclaiming the institutional roots of international border law suggests a shift from a unilateral to a cooperative default setting. Unilateral border hardening has been rampant globally, from the construction of border walls and fences to the deployment of military troops in peace time.102
Max Mendez-Parra & Linda Calabrese, One-stop Border Posts in East Africa, ODI (July 2023), https://cdn.odi.org/media/documents/Report_-_One-stop_border_posts_in_East_Africa_-_July_2023.pdf[https://perma.cc/65WY-LW77](emphasizing the innovations in trade cooperation while not addressing migration).
Tex. Dep’t of Transp., Texas-Mexico Border Transportation Master Plan 1-1 (2021), https://library.ctr.utexas.edu/Presto/content/Detail.aspx?ctID=UHVibGljYXRpb25fMTE2MTA%3D&rID=MzMyNjU%3D&ssid=c2NyZWVuSURfMjEzMjI%3D&bmdc=MQ==[https://perma.cc/3G3A-36T3].These numbers are based on inflation adjusted to 2019 dollars. Id. (citing Trade in Goods with Mexico, U.S. Census Bureau (2023), https://www.census.gov/foreign-trade/balance/c2010.html[https://perma.cc/WJ3W-JWEV]).
Ana Gonzales-Barrera, Before COVID-19, More Mexicans Came to the U.S. Than Left for Mexico for the First Time in Years, Pew Rsch. Ctr. (July 9, 2021), https://www.pewresearch.org/short-reads/2021/07/09/before-covid-19-more-mexicans-came-to-the-u-s-than-left-for-mexico-for-the-first-time-in-years/[https://perma.cc/LA62-S6Z2].
Vaughan Lowe, International law 151 (2007).
Hints at a more neighborly approach along these lines are evident in FACT SHEET: Second Meeting of the U.S.-Mexico High-Level Security Dialogue, The White House (Oct.13, 2022), https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefing-room/statements-releases/2022/10/13/fact-sheet-second-meeting-of-the-u-s-mexico-high-level-security-dialogue/[https://perma.cc/CU6Q-GZNA].
See Kristen E. Eichensehr & Cathy Hwang, National Security Creep in Corporate Transactions, 123 Colum. L. Rev. 549 (2023).
Second, reclaiming the institutional roots of international border law requires states to be transparent about what constitutes a threat to national security and then to make a case to domestic and international audiences that national security is at stake in important ways in the border zone. In only a very few cases will national security truly be at stake. Where it is, states must define the national security threat, and then use extraordinary means only as a necessity and only in proportion to the danger to the nation as a whole. Unless a clear and reasonable distinction is made, there is a real risk of “national security creep,” by which I mean the state’s “increasingly broad claims about what constitutes national security.”108
See, e.g., Maureen Meyer et al., Not a National Security Crisis: The U.S.-Mexico Border and Humanitarian Concerns, Seen from El Paso, WOLA, (Oct. 2016) https://www.wola.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/10/WOLA_NoNationalSecurityCrisis_October2016.pdf[https://perma.cc/9CS7-U5RX] (arguing that there is no “national security” crisis, but rather a humanitarian crisis at the southern U.S. border).
A crucial step to stop the creep is to sort out national security threats from humanitarian crises and respond appropriately.109
See Carla N. Argueta, Cong. Rsch. Serv., R42138 , Border Security: Immigration Enforcement Between Ports of Entry 3 (2016).
The U.N. Special Rapporteur on Torture has reported that torture and other inhuman acts are in many cases “the direct or indirect result of policies and practices adopted by States with a view to deterring, punishing or controlling irregular migration.” Rep. of the Special Rapporteur on Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment, at 16, U.N. Doc. A/HRC/37/50 (2018).
Camilo Montoya-Galvez & Nicole Sganga, Border Patrol Agents on Horseback Used “Unnecessary” Force Against Haitian Migrants Last Year, Investigators Find, CBS News (July 8, 2022), https://www.cbsnews.com/news/border-patrol-agents-on-horseback-used-unnecessary-force-against-haitian-migrants-last-year-investigators-find/[https://perma.cc/XGQ8-PHDZ].
Acacia Coronado, Texas Trooper’s Accounts of Bloodied and Fainting Migrants on US-Mexico Border Unleashes Criticism, AP (July 18, 2023), https://apnews.com/article/texas-border-razor-wire-fainting-7aa811baf2708b89a0316804c3f2e35e[https://perma.cc/V2L6-ZLN9].
SeeHuman Costs of Border Control, Univ. Amsterdam, http://www.borderdeaths.org/?page_id=5[https://perma.cc/JJ4N-EBMK](last visited Sept. 10, 2023). This is a database of migrant deaths in the Mediterranean region, which concentrates on the border management system of Spain, Gibraltar, Italy, Malta, and Greece.
Gino Pauselli & Beth A. Simmons, From Physical Barriers to Physical Abuse: Border Hardening and Torture Allegations (forthcoming 2023) (on file with author).
Erika Sigvardsdotter et al., Prevalence of Torture and Other War-Related Traumatic Events in Forced Migrants: A Systematic Review, 26 J. on Rehab. Torture Victims & Prevention Torture 41 (2016).
Department of State and Department of Homeland Security Announce Additional Sweeping Measures to Humanely Manage Border through Deterrence, Enforcement, and Diplomacy, U.S. Dep’t of State (May 10, 2023). https://www.state.gov/department-of-state-and-department-of-homeland-security-announce-additional-sweeping-measures-to-humanely-manage-border-through-deterrence-enforcement-and-diplomacy/[https://perma.cc/8NSX-X9G8].
Several practices would move the ball forward for human rights protections in and around border areas. Far from suspending human rights protections, states should develop and nurture neighborly routines for safeguarding them. Some have begun to develop policies to do so. Although clinging to the strategy of deterrence, the U.S. Department of Homeland Security announced policies in May 2023 to “humanely manage the border through deterrence, enforcement, and diplomacy,”117
Fundamental Rights at Frontex, Frontex, https://frontex.europa.eu/fundamental-rights/fundamental-rights-at-frontex/fundamental-rights-at-frontex/#:~:text=Frontex%20strictly%20adheres%20to%20the,Refugees%20and%20its%201967%20Protocol[https://perma.cc/S4UG-87EM](last visited Sept. 10, 2023).
Id.
See Elizabeth M. Bruch, Open or Closed: Balancing Border Policy with Human Rights, 96 Ky. L. J. 197 (2007).
Reconceptualizing international borders as cooperative institutions suggests recalibration of national security concerns relating to borders. Borders should not be thought of as national security zones by default. Readiness needs to be tempered with a sober assessment of what exactly the risk to national security is and what is causing it. When it comes to extraordinary levels of undocumented migration, intensified enforcement should be addressed first and foremost through well-designed immigration policies. In the rarest situations, border securitization and even militarization may be needed. When this is the case, extraordinary actions should at a minimum be monitored and follow customary practices of proportionality and necessity.
V. Conclusion
TOPA great many observers and scholars have concluded that there is a growing imbalance between sovereign rights of states to control their borders and human rights concerns. Twentieth century expansion of such rights has long been in tension with “traditional” doctrines of state sovereignty,120
See Moria Paz, Between the Kingdom and the Desert Sun: Human Rights, Immigration, and Border Walls, 34 Berkeley J. Int’l L. 1 (2016).
Mattias Kumm, Sovereignty and the Right to Be Left Alone: Subsidiarity, Justice-Sensitive Externalities and the Proper Domain of the Consent Requirement in International Law, 79 Law & Contemp. Probs. 239, 255–57 (2016).
SeeBenvenisti, supra note 11.
This Article has suggested there is yet another, more state-centric, way to approach what is becoming an untenable conflict between international human rights and the presumed right of sovereign states to control their borders at all costs. This move involves understanding international borders as fundamentally cooperative institutions chosen by sovereign states to govern their mutual relations. Borders in this conception are ways to achieve the collective good of international stability, as we have seen from the unusual exceptions made for border agreements in treaty law and the extraordinary value states place on settled borders in multilateral law. Territorial sovereignty, in this understanding, is exclusive. However, the institutions created to establish understandings to manage proximate sovereignty are shared. Sovereignty divides space into “yours” and “mine.” But the border as an institution is ours. States have obligations to each other and to border residents and crossers to continue the cooperative traditions of international bordering.
As institutions, borders are not only territorial. They are also relational. They regulate and shape how nations and populations interact. They do not create sovereignty, which I have argued is not logically or legally dependent on bordering; sovereign states can and have historically had fuzzy and permeable borders and yet enjoyed sovereign status. Rather, they create and coordinate relationships of neighborliness. Obligations of neighborliness are traditionally negative, but increasingly recognized as positive. The public international law of neighborliness is a real thing that states have practiced, developed, committed to, and litigated over many decades. It suggests a state-based rationale for a broad range of cooperative border practices. The primary positive duty of good neighborliness is to live up to all obligations undertaken in international law. International human rights obligations are paramount among such obligations.
The public international law of neighborliness is an additional door through which international human rights law must claim entry. While there is room for theorizing more cosmopolitan approaches, it makes sense to not concede the cooperative foundations of international borders to call for the respect of universal international human rights, everywhere. Deference to border security in places and for people most impacted by jurisdictional disjunctures cannot be an acceptable default. Before accepting border security as a rationale for inscrutable state prerogatives, states should be held to their own institutions of neighborliness.
- 1SeeHernandez v. Mesa, 140 S. Ct. 735, 740–41 (2020).
- 2Id. at 746.
- 3Id. at 739.
- 4Calculated using the LandScan database. See LandScan, Oak Ridge Nat’l Laboratory (2022), https://www.ornl.gov/project/landscan[https://perma.cc/53ZH-KWTF](last visited August 31, 2023). Approximately ninety-nine million people (1.32%) live within 5 kilometers, 200 million people (2.7%) within 10 kilometers, and more than 600 million people (8.05%) live within 30 kilometers of an international land border. These figures exclude coastlines.
- 5Calculations based on data from author’s database of border crossings and population from LandScan. See LandScan, Oak Ridge Nat’l Laboratory (2022), https://landscan.ornl.gov/[https://perma.cc/5KBS-TXPP](last visited Aug. 31, 2023).
- 6Tanvi Misra, CityLab/MapLab: Inside the Massive U.S. ‘Borderzone’, Bloomberg (May 14, 2018), https://www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2018-05-14/mapping-who-lives-in-border-patrol-s-100-mile-zone[https://perma.cc/RX9Y-YM4L].
- 7UNWTO World Tourism Barometer and Statistical Annex, UNWTO eLibrary(Jan. 2020), https://www.e-unwto.org/doi/abs/10.18111/wtobarometereng.2020.18.1.1[https://perma.cc/7CTN-25LT].
- 8See, e.g., Convention on Long-range Transboundary Air Pollution, Nov. 13, 1979, 1302 U.N.T.S. 217, https://treaties.un.org/doc/Treaties/1979/11/19791113%2004-16%20PM/Ch_XXVII_01p.pdf[https://perma.cc/43M9-HFR4].
- 9OECD, Illicit Trade: Converging Criminal Networks 5 (2016), https://read.oecd-ilibrary.org/governance/charting-illicit-trade_9789264251847-en#page1[https://perma.cc/3ZXA-N2BG].
- 10Michael Kenwick & Beth A. Simmons, Pandemic Response as Border Politics, 74 Int’l Org. E36, E52 (2020). Positive externalities are possible as well. For example, if one country has an effective vaccine campaign it can potentially reduce infection rates in a neighboring state.
- 11Eyal Benvenisti, Sovereigns as Trustees of Humanity: On the Accountability of States to Foreign Stakeholders, 107 Am. J. Int’l L. 295, 328 (2013).
- 12The most obvious case is that of the European Union, and Frontex is an example. Note, however, that cooperation between states can be normatively problematic. For the critique of the legitimacy of European cooperation, see Hallvard Sandven, The Practice and Legitimacy of Border Control, Am. J. Pol. Sci. 1, 4 (2022). With respect to North America, see Matthew Longo, From Sovereignty to Imperium: Borders, Frontiers and the Specter of Neo-Imperialism, 22 Geopolitics 758, 768 (2017).
- 13See Michael Kenwick et al., Infrastructure and Authority at the State’s Edge: The Border Crossings of the World Dataset, J. Peace Rsch. (forthcoming) (on file with author).
- 14This point is developed and supported with examples in Michael R Kenwick et al., Border Walls as Cooperation Failures, (U. Pa. L. Sch., Pub. L. Rsch. Paper No. 23-13, 2023), https://ssrn.com/abstract=4343982[https://perma.cc/CHN9-HE6N].It is important to acknowledge that States may decide to govern some aspects of their shared border cooperatively, as the United States and Mexico have done in the past, then suddenly shift to a more unilateral stance. Matthew Longo identifies “co-bordering” as a global trend. Matthew Longo, The Politics of Borders: Sovereignty, Security, and the Citizen After 9/11, at 121 (2017).
- 15For descriptive statistics, see Kenwick et al., supra note 14. See also Beth A. Simmons & Michael Kenwick, Border Orientation in a Globalizing World: Concept and Measurement, 66 Am. J. Pol. Sci. 853, 861 (2022); Ron E. Hassner & Jason Wittenberg, Barriers to Entry: Who Builds Fortified Boundaries and Why?, 40 Int’l Sec. 157, 166 (2015); Élisabeth Vallet & Charles-Philippe David, Introduction: The (Re)Building of the Wall in International Relations, 27 J. Borderlands Stud. 111, 113 (2012); David B Carter & Paul Poast, Why Do States Build Walls? Political Economy, Security, and Border Stability, 61 J. Conflict Resol. 239, 249 (2017).
- 16Sean M. Topping, Defying Schengen through Internal Border Controls: Acts of National Risk-Taking or Violations of International Law at the Heart of Europe, 48 Geo. J. Int’l L. 331, 333 (2016).
- 17For a 28-page list of all border controls implemented by members pursuant to Article 25 and 28 et seq. of the Schengen Borders Code, see Temporary Reintroduction of Border Control, European Comm’n Migration & Home Affairs, https://home-affairs.ec.europa.eu/policies/schengen-borders-and-visa/schengen-area/temporary-reintroduction-border-control_en[https://perma.cc/W5ZH-3AAV](last visited Sept. 18, 2023).
- 18On U.S. policy in the Americas, see Nancy Hiemstra, Pushing the US-Mexico Border South: United States’ Immigration Policing Throughout the Americas, 5 Int’l J. Migration & Border Stud. 44 (2019). On Australia, see Amy Nethery et al., Exporting Detention: Australia-Funded Immigration Detention in Indonesia, 26 J. Refugee Stud. 88 (2013). On Europe, see Anneliese Baldaccini, Extraterritorial Border Controls in the EU: The Role of Frontex in Operations at Sea, in Extraterritorial immigration control 229 (2010); Maribel Casas-Cortes et al., ‘Good Neighbours Make Good Fences’: Seahorse Operations, Border Externalization and Extra-Territoriality, 23 Eur. Urb. & Reg’l Stud. 1 (2016).
- 19Jaya Ramji-Nogales & Iris Goldner Lang, Freedom of Movement, Migration, and Borders, 19 J. Hum. Rts. 593, 593 (2020).
- 20A prominent U.S. example includes The White House, National Security Presidential Directive (NSPD-22) Combating Trafficking in Persons (2002), https://ctip.defense.gov/Portals/12/Documents/NSPD-22.pdf [https://perma.cc/9H5T-L89E].
- 21An example at the international level is the establishment of the United Nations Office of Counter-Terrorism, through the adoption of G.A. Res. 71/291 (June 15, 2017). Border security is one of the organization’s key capacity-building emphases. SeeWhat We Do, U.N. Off. of Counter-Terrorism, https://www.un.org/counterterrorism/what-we-do[https://perma.cc/S5BU-B8UT](last visited Sept. 11, 2023).
- 22Figures at a Glance,UNCHR, The UN Refugee Agency (June 14, 2023), https://www.unhcr.org/about-unhcr/who-we-are/figures-glance[https://perma.cc/5N76-RDKY].
- 23Céline Cantat et al., Migration as Crisis, 67 Am. Behav. Scientist (forthcoming 2023) (manuscript at 1) (finding that “migration has become inseparable from a narrative of crisis.”).
- 24Beth A. Simmons & Robert Shaffer, Border Anxiety in International Discourse, Am. J. Pol. Sci. (forthcoming) (on file with author) (defining border anxiety as “a heightened sense of instability or vulnerability perceived to be linked with a broad range of cross-border phenomena,” and emphasizing that it can often be exaggerated).
- 25See generally David A. Shirk, The Escalation of US–Mexico Border Enforcement, in Borders & Border Walls: In-Security, Symbolism, Vulnerabilities (Andréanne Bissonnette & Élisabeth Vallet eds., 2020).
- 26For the Office of Home Affairs’ campaign page, see Operation Sovereign Borders, Australian Gov’t, https://osb.homeaffairs.gov.au/[https://perma.cc/YCW8-95P7](last visited Sept. 11, 2023).
- 27Introduced as the “Sovereign Borders Bill” in 2020. Sovereign Borders: International Asylum Comparisons Report, Home Office (Sept. 2020), https://freemovement.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/2022/11/Annex-A-Sovereign-Borders-International-Asylum-Comparisons-Report-Section-1-Drivers-and-impact-on-asylum-migration-journeys.pdf[https://perma.cc/4P9R-UKQF].
- 28Matina Stevis-Gridneff, E.U. Border Agency Accused of Covering Up Migrant Pushback in Greece, N.Y. Times (July 18, 2021), https://www.nytimes.com/2020/11/26/world/europe/frontex-migrants-pushback-greece.html[https://perma.cc/2QHE-2VC5](referring to “a conundrum at the core of E.U. ambitions to tighten external borders by pooling resources and involving the bloc in the sensitive, zealously shielded work of sovereign border guards”).
- 29Google Ngrams, https://books.google.com/ngrams/[https://perma.cc/ZCW9-L3V9](last visited Sept. 11, 2023).
- 30For elaboration, see the discussion in Jack Goldsmith, Review: Sovereignty, International Relations Theory, and International Law, 52 Stan. L. Rev. 959 (2000).
- 31See, e.g., Remarks by President Trump at the 45th Mile of New Border Wall, Reynosa-McAllen, TX, The White House (Jan. 12, 2021), https://trumpwhitehouse.archives.gov/briefings-statements/remarks-president-trump-45th-mile-new-border-wall-reynosa-mcallen-tx/) [https://perma.cc/B8ZJ-G3ED].
- 32Commonly cited are the words of Max Huber, arbitrator in Island of Palmas (U.S. v. Neth.), 2 U.N. Rep. Intl. Arb. Awards 821, 838 (1928): “Sovereignty in the relations between states signifies independence. Independence in regard to a portion of the globe is the right to exercise there, to the exclusion of any other states, the function of a state.” See also Corfu Channel (U.K. v. Alb.), Judgment, 1949 I.C.J. 39, 43 (Apr. 9) (“By sovereignty, we understand the whole body of rights and attributes which a state possesses in its territory, to the exclusion of all other states, and also in its relations with other states.”).
- 33Helmut Steinberger, Sovereignty, 10 Encyclopedia Disp. Installment 397, 408 (1987).
- 34North Sea Continental Shelf (Ger. v. Den./Ger. v. Neth.), Judgment, 1969 I.C.J. 3, ¶ 46 (Feb. 20). See also Giuseppe Nesi, Boundaries, in Research Handbook on Territorial Disputes in International Law 193, 195 (Marcelo Kohen & Mamadou Hébié eds., 2018) (arguing that “a boundary has no effect on the existence of a state”).
- 35Montevideo Convention on Rights and Duties of States adopted by the Seventh International Conference of American States art. I, Dec. 26, 1933, 165 L.N.T.S. 19 (stating that a “defined territory” is one of the qualifications a “state as a person of international law should possess[]” according to the most widely accepted international convention on statehood).
- 36For example, borders are not mentioned in the G.A. Res. 375 (IV), (Dec. 6, 1949).
- 37U.N. Charter art. 2, ¶ 4.
- 38SeeBeth A. Simmons & Hein E. Goemans, Built on Borders: Tensions with the Institution Liberalism (Thought It) Left Behind, 75 Int’l Org. 387, 389–91 (2021).
- 39The principle of stability is traditionally deemed as the criterion for interpreting boundary treaties. See Charles de Visscher, Problèmes De Confins en Droit International Public 28 (1969).
- 40Dubai/SharjahBorder Arbitration, 91 Int’l L. Rep. 543, 578 (2009).
- 41Malcolm N. Shaw, Boundary Treaties and Their Interpretation, 5 Queen Mary Stud. Int’l L. 239, 239 (2012) (claiming in his opening paragraph that “[b]oundary treaties are treaties, but are distinctive. They constitute a special category of treaties”).
- 42There is vast empirical literature in international relations supporting this point. For an early statement and findings, see John Vasquez & Marie Henehan, Territorial Disputes and the Probability of War, 1816–1992, 38 J. Peace Rsch. 123 (2001).
- 43These numbers reflect the total number of interstate land borders in “direct contiguity,” generated from the Correlates of War Dataset. Data Sets, Correlates of War, http://www.correlatesofwar.org/data-sets[https://perma.cc/YEZ4-JA86](last visited Sept. 11, 2023). See Beth A. Simmons, Border Rules, 21 Int’l Stud. Rev. 256, 260 fig.1 (2019).
- 44Dan Altman, The Evolution of Territorial Conquest After 1945 and the Limits of the Territorial Integrity Norm, 74 Int’l Org. 490, 490 (2020).
- 45Kenneth A. Schultz, What’s in a Claim? De Jure Versus De Facto Borders in Interstate Territorial Disputes, 58 J. Conflict Resol. 1059, 1059 (2014). (finding that “among states that have homeland territory disputes, the adoption of a legally binding border is associated with a significant reduction in the likelihood of future militarized conflict over the territory”). Seealso Nesi, supra note 34, at 150 (concluding that “[s]tates are more capable of peacefully carrying their relations and exercising sovereign rights when their territory is well defined—that is to say, when it can be easily identified”).
- 46Shaw, supra note 41, at 242.
- 47Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, May 23, 1969, 1155 U.N.T.S. 331.
- 48Id.
- 49Humphrey Waldock, Fifth Report on the Law of Treaties, 2 Y.B. Int’l L. Comm’n 1, 43 (1966).
- 50Humphrey Waldock, Sixth Report on the Law of Treaties, 2 Y.B. Int’l L. Comm’n 51, 92–93 (1966).
- 51Shaw, supra note 41, at 259 (in the context of the Eritrea-Ethiopia boundary commission).
- 52Vienna Convention on Succession of States in respect of Treaties art. 11, Nov. 6, 1996, 1946 U.N.T.S. 3 [hereinafter Vienna Convention].
- 53United States v. Texas, 143 U.S. 621 (1892) (holding that upon independence in 1840, Texas’s boundary with the United States was that established by treaty with Mexico in 1828).
- 54Temple of Preah Vihear, (Cambodia v. Thai.), Judgment, 1962 I.C.J. 6 (June 15) (ruling that Cambodia succeeded to a 1904 boundary treaty concluded by France for Cambodia and Siam).
- 55Vienna Convention, supranote 52, at art. 16 (“A newly independent State is not bound to maintain in force, or to become a party to, any treaty by reason only of the fact that at the date of the succession of States the treaty was in force in respect of the territory to which the succession of States relates.”).
- 56Maurizio Ragazzi, Conference on Yugoslavia Arbitration Commission: Opinions on Questions Arising From the Dissolution of Yugoslavia, 31 Int’l Legal Materials 1488, 1499 (1992).
- 57Eritrea v. Yemen, 22 U.N. Rep. Intl. Arb. Awards 209, ¶ 153 (1998).
- 58Shaw, supra note 41, at 239. There is growing consensus that boundary treaties indeed can bind third parties. See,e.g., Ulf Linderfalk, International Legal Hierarchy Revisited–The Status of Obligations Erga Omnes, 80 Nordic J. Int’l L. 1, 15 (2011).
- 59See Humphrey Waldock, Third Report on the Law of Treaties, 2 Y.B. Int’l L. Comm’n 5, 26–31 (1964).
- 60Importantly, however, the International Court of Justice has held that joint territorial regimes between two states do not dispose of the rights of independent Third Parties. See Territorial and Maritime Dispute (Nicar. v. Colom.), Judgment, 2012 I.C.J. 624, ¶ 227 (Nov. 19).
- "
- 62Notably, resolving border and territorial disputes is considered an important factor for joining some international organizations such as NATO and the European Union. For NATO, settling such disputes “would be a factor in determining whether to invite a state to join the Alliance.” Study on NATO Enlargement, NATO (Nov. 5, 2008), https://www.nato.int/cps/en/natohq/official_texts_24733.htm[https://perma.cc/C8PQ-D4XK].
- 63On “objective regimes” and their effect on third parties, see Reports of the International Law Commission on the Second Part of its Seven-Teenth Session and on its Eighteenth Session, 2 Y.B. Int’l L. Comm’n 169, 231 (1966); see also Arnold D. McNair, The Functions and Differing Legal Character of Treaties, 11 Brit. Y.B. Int’l L. 100, 102–03 (1930). Somewhat skeptically, see Carlos Fernández de Casadevante Romani, Objective Regime, in 7 Max Planck Encyclopedia Pub. Int’l L. 912 (2010).
- 64Swiss permanent armed neutrality was internationally recognized at the Congress of Vienna in 1815 by Russia, England, Prussia, Austria, and France. Thomas Curson Hansard, In Congress, At Vienna, June 8, 1815, 32 Parliamentary Debates from Year 1803 to Present Time 71, 182 (1816).
- 65Convention Relating to the Non-Fortification and Neutralization of the Aaland Islands, Apr. 6, 1922, 9 L.N.T.S. 211.
- 66Richard A. Barnes, Objective Regimes Revisited, 9 Asian Y.B. Int’l L. 97, 98 (2000).As examples, Barnes analyzes Antarctica, Outer Space, the Deep Seabed, the High Seas, and “Zones of Peace.” Id. at 106.
- 67U.N. Charter art. 2 ¶ 4.
- 68Hernandez v. Mesa, 582 U.S. 548, 557 (2017) (vacating and remanding the Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit’s decision affirming the District Court’s dismissal of the parents’ claims, and directing the Court of Appeals to address several questions); Hernandez v. Mesa, 130 S Ct. 735 (2020) (confirming the judgment of the Court of Appeals).
- 69Hernandez, 582 U.S. 548, 557 (2017) (Breyer, J., dissenting).
- 70Id. at 558.
- 71Id. at 559.
- 72See generally Hernandez, 130 S Ct. at 756–57 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting).
- 73Daniel-Erasmus Khan, Territory and Boundaries, in The Oxford Handbook of the History of International Law 225, 234 (Bardo Fassbender & Anne Peters eds., 2012).
- 74Emer de Vattel, The Law of Nations 308 (Béla Kapossy & Richard Whatmore eds., 2008).
- 75Martina Löw & Gunter Weidenhaus, Borders That Relate: Conceptualizing Boundaries in Relational Space, 65 Current Socio. 553, 555 (2017).
- "Anssi Paasi, Border Studies Reanimated: Going Beyond the Territorial/Relational Divide, 44 Env’t & Plan. A 2303 (2012). Paasi usefully describes a boundary as a sociological institution with both territorial and relational aspects. He sees borders not as “static ‘things’” but rather as “dynamic, unfolding relations.” Id. at 2304.
- 77See Andreas Müller, Territorial Borders as Institutions: Functional Change and the Spatial Division of Authority, 15 Eur. Soc’y 353, 365 (2013) (describing “borders as reciprocal restrictions of influence”).
- 78Delimitation is the process of negotiating the location of an international border, and demarcation is how it is made visible in the landscape, e.g., through the placement of markers, signs, monuments, etc.
- 79Nail is explicit about these ongoing aspects of dynamic bordering: “[B]order technologies must be maintained, reproduced, refueled, defended, started up, paid for, repaired, and so on. . . . Management in some form or another has always been part of their existence.” Nail, supra note 76, at 7.
- 80On the international (and E.U.) law of good neighborliness, see Elena Basheska & Dimitry Kochenov, The Meso Level: Means of Interaction between EU and International Law ‘Good Fences Make Good Neighbors’ and Beyond . . . Two Faces of the Good Neighbourliness Principle, 35 Y.B. Eur. L. 562, 564 (2016) (formulating the obligation of good neighborliness as a “general principle [to be] accepted by all UN members”).
- 81U.N. Charter pmbl.
- 82Id. at art. 74. (“Members of the United Nations also agree that their policy in respect of the territories to which this Chapter applies, no less than in respect of their metropolitan areas, must be based on the general principle of good-neighborliness, due account being taken of the interests and well-being of the rest of the world, in social, economic, and commercial matters.”).
- 83Laurence Boisson de Chazournes & Danio Campanelli, Neighbour States, in 7 Max Planck Encyclopedia Pub. Int’l L. 600, ¶ 6. (2006). Likewise, Tadeusz Gadkowski stresses that “[t]he good-neighborliness principle is thus undoubtedly an expression of the interdependence of the rights and interests of States bordering on each other and the requirement ensuing from this, namely that each State limit the activities that may cause damage outside its territory.” Tadeusz Gadkowski, The Principle of Good-Neighbourliness in International Nuclear Law, 12 Przegląd Prawniczy Uniwersytetu im. Adama Mickiewicza 265, 267 (2021)(emphasis added).
- 84Paraphrasing the Declaration on Principles of International Law Concerning Friendly Relations and Cooperation Among States in Accordance with the UN Charter. G.A. Res. 2625 (XXV) (Oct. 24, 1970) [hereinafter The Declaration on Friendly Relations]. The Declaration on Friendly Relations, like the U.N. Charter as a whole, is based on the assumption of the “inviolability of territorial integrity.”
- 85See Bandung Conference: Asia-Africa 1955, ENCYCLOPEDIA BRITANNICA, https://www.britannica.com/event/Bandung-Conference[https://perma.cc/2CYQ-M43Q](last visited Oct. 10, 2023) (adopting a declaration on the promotion of world peace and cooperation). In addition, at least nine United Nations General Assembly (UNGA) resolutions that have grappled with defining good neighborliness. See Basheska & Kochenov, supra note 81, at 574.
- 86See Gadkowski,supra note 84.
- 87Bruno Simma, The Charter of the United Nations 1097 (1995) (concluding that “[t]he principle of good neighborliness rather sets a general, though nonetheless legally binding aim for policy; it is thus more than just a political principle.”); Boisson de Chazournes & Campanelli, supra note 84, ¶ 28 (concluding that “the concept of good neighborliness possesses some legal contours, though imprecise.”).
- 88In the Haya de la Torre case, the ICJ suggested that the parties should “find a practical and satisfactory solution by seeking guidance from those considerations of courtesy and good neighborliness which, in matters of asylum . . . ,” thus nudging states in Latin America to conclude the Caracas Convention on Diplomatic Asylum in 1954. Haya de la Torre (Colom. v. Peru), Judgment, 1951 I.C.J. 71, 83 (June 13).
- 89Malgosia Fitzmaurice & Olufemi Elias, Watercourse Co-operation in Northern Europe: A Model for the Future (2004). For the development of community of interest with respect to international watercourses, for example, see id. at 13–15.
- 90Edgardo Sobenes et al. The Environment Through the Lens of International Courts and Tribunals 549–59 (2022);
- 91Joanna Kulesza, Human Rights Due Diligence, 30 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 265 (2021) (discussing this in the context of due diligence and international liability concepts).
- 92Corfu Channel (U.K. v. Alb.), Judgment, 1949 I.C.J. 4, 22 (Apr. 9).
- 93Gabˇcíkovo-Nagymaros Project (Hung./Slovk.), Judgment, 1997 I.C.J. 7, ¶ 142 (Sept. 25).
- 94MOX Plant (Ir. V. U.K.), Case no. 10, Order of Dec. 3, 2001, 2001 ITLOS Rep. 95. Especially see the Separate Opinion of Judge Rudiger Wolfrum. Id. at 135.
- 95Sobenes, supra note 91, at 553. Due diligence requirements are still being formulated. See Draft Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts, 2 Y.B. Int’l L. Comm’n 26 (2001), discussed in Kulesza,supra note 92.
- 96Sobenes, supra note 91, at 556.
- 97Damiano Canale, Walled Borders, Territoriality and Sovereignty: A Typology, 1 Athena – Critical Inquiries L., Phil. & Globalization 37, 47 (2021).
- 98Id. (quotations omitted).
- 99Löw & Weidenhaus, supra note 75, at 557; Ran Hirschl & Ayelet Shachar, Spatial Statism, 17 Int’l J. Const. L. 387, 391 (2019) (emphasizing states’ use of law to restrict various forms of mobility by creating a “new configuration” of the Weberian state).
- 100International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, Dec. 16, 1966, 999 U.N.T.S. 171.
- 101See, e.g., Kenwick et al., supra note 14, (presenting evidence that many border hardening projects are taken without consultation with a neighboring state and sometimes explicitly against their preferences).
- 102Max Mendez-Parra & Linda Calabrese, One-stop Border Posts in East Africa, ODI (July 2023), https://cdn.odi.org/media/documents/Report_-_One-stop_border_posts_in_East_Africa_-_July_2023.pdf[https://perma.cc/65WY-LW77](emphasizing the innovations in trade cooperation while not addressing migration).
- 103Tex. Dep’t of Transp., Texas-Mexico Border Transportation Master Plan 1-1 (2021), https://library.ctr.utexas.edu/Presto/content/Detail.aspx?ctID=UHVibGljYXRpb25fMTE2MTA%3D&rID=MzMyNjU%3D&ssid=c2NyZWVuSURfMjEzMjI%3D&bmdc=MQ==[https://perma.cc/3G3A-36T3].These numbers are based on inflation adjusted to 2019 dollars. Id. (citing Trade in Goods with Mexico, U.S. Census Bureau (2023), https://www.census.gov/foreign-trade/balance/c2010.html[https://perma.cc/WJ3W-JWEV]).
- 104Ana Gonzales-Barrera, Before COVID-19, More Mexicans Came to the U.S. Than Left for Mexico for the First Time in Years, Pew Rsch. Ctr. (July 9, 2021), https://www.pewresearch.org/short-reads/2021/07/09/before-covid-19-more-mexicans-came-to-the-u-s-than-left-for-mexico-for-the-first-time-in-years/[https://perma.cc/LA62-S6Z2].
- 105Vaughan Lowe, International law 151 (2007).
- 106Hints at a more neighborly approach along these lines are evident in FACT SHEET: Second Meeting of the U.S.-Mexico High-Level Security Dialogue, The White House (Oct.13, 2022), https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefing-room/statements-releases/2022/10/13/fact-sheet-second-meeting-of-the-u-s-mexico-high-level-security-dialogue/[https://perma.cc/CU6Q-GZNA].
- 107See Kristen E. Eichensehr & Cathy Hwang, National Security Creep in Corporate Transactions, 123 Colum. L. Rev. 549 (2023).
- 108See, e.g., Maureen Meyer et al., Not a National Security Crisis: The U.S.-Mexico Border and Humanitarian Concerns, Seen from El Paso, WOLA, (Oct. 2016) https://www.wola.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/10/WOLA_NoNationalSecurityCrisis_October2016.pdf[https://perma.cc/9CS7-U5RX] (arguing that there is no “national security” crisis, but rather a humanitarian crisis at the southern U.S. border).
- 109See Carla N. Argueta, Cong. Rsch. Serv., R42138 , Border Security: Immigration Enforcement Between Ports of Entry 3 (2016).
- 110The U.N. Special Rapporteur on Torture has reported that torture and other inhuman acts are in many cases “the direct or indirect result of policies and practices adopted by States with a view to deterring, punishing or controlling irregular migration.” Rep. of the Special Rapporteur on Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment, at 16, U.N. Doc. A/HRC/37/50 (2018).
- 111Camilo Montoya-Galvez & Nicole Sganga, Border Patrol Agents on Horseback Used “Unnecessary” Force Against Haitian Migrants Last Year, Investigators Find, CBS News (July 8, 2022), https://www.cbsnews.com/news/border-patrol-agents-on-horseback-used-unnecessary-force-against-haitian-migrants-last-year-investigators-find/[https://perma.cc/XGQ8-PHDZ].
- 112Acacia Coronado, Texas Trooper’s Accounts of Bloodied and Fainting Migrants on US-Mexico Border Unleashes Criticism, AP (July 18, 2023), https://apnews.com/article/texas-border-razor-wire-fainting-7aa811baf2708b89a0316804c3f2e35e[https://perma.cc/V2L6-ZLN9].
- 113SeeHuman Costs of Border Control, Univ. Amsterdam, http://www.borderdeaths.org/?page_id=5[https://perma.cc/JJ4N-EBMK](last visited Sept. 10, 2023). This is a database of migrant deaths in the Mediterranean region, which concentrates on the border management system of Spain, Gibraltar, Italy, Malta, and Greece.
- 114Gino Pauselli & Beth A. Simmons, From Physical Barriers to Physical Abuse: Border Hardening and Torture Allegations (forthcoming 2023) (on file with author).
- 115Erika Sigvardsdotter et al., Prevalence of Torture and Other War-Related Traumatic Events in Forced Migrants: A Systematic Review, 26 J. on Rehab. Torture Victims & Prevention Torture 41 (2016).
- 116Department of State and Department of Homeland Security Announce Additional Sweeping Measures to Humanely Manage Border through Deterrence, Enforcement, and Diplomacy, U.S. Dep’t of State (May 10, 2023). https://www.state.gov/department-of-state-and-department-of-homeland-security-announce-additional-sweeping-measures-to-humanely-manage-border-through-deterrence-enforcement-and-diplomacy/[https://perma.cc/8NSX-X9G8].
- 117Fundamental Rights at Frontex, Frontex, https://frontex.europa.eu/fundamental-rights/fundamental-rights-at-frontex/fundamental-rights-at-frontex/#:~:text=Frontex%20strictly%20adheres%20to%20the,Refugees%20and%20its%201967%20Protocol[https://perma.cc/S4UG-87EM](last visited Sept. 10, 2023).
- 118Id.
- 119See Elizabeth M. Bruch, Open or Closed: Balancing Border Policy with Human Rights, 96 Ky. L. J. 197 (2007).
- 120See Moria Paz, Between the Kingdom and the Desert Sun: Human Rights, Immigration, and Border Walls, 34 Berkeley J. Int’l L. 1 (2016).
- 121Mattias Kumm, Sovereignty and the Right to Be Left Alone: Subsidiarity, Justice-Sensitive Externalities and the Proper Domain of the Consent Requirement in International Law, 79 Law & Contemp. Probs. 239, 255–57 (2016).
- 122SeeBenvenisti, supra note 11.